Back

BusyBeaver(6) Is Quite Large

234 points20 hoursscottaaronson.blog
tromp17 hours ago

People on the bbchallenge Discord server are keen to speculate on how many Turing Machine states are needed to surpass Graham's Number, which is vastly larger than the 2^^2^^2^^9 achieved by the latest BB(6) champion.

We know from the functional busy beaver [1] that Graham behaviour can come surprisingly early; a 49-bit lambda term suffices. There are only 77519927606 closed lambda terms of at most that size [2], compared to 4^12*23836540=399910780272640 unique 6-state Turing Machines [3].

With the achievement of pentation in only 6 states, several people now believe that 7 states should suffice to surpass Graham's. I would still find that rather surprising. A few days ago, I made a large bet with one of them on whether we would see proof of BB(7)>Graham's within the next 10 years.

What do people here think?

[1] https://oeis.org/A333479

[2] https://oeis.org/A114852

[3] https://oeis.org/A107668

gpm17 hours ago

I can't pretend to be an expert, but I'll argue BB(7) is probably larger than Graham's number.

BB has to grow faster than any computable sequence. What exactly that means concretely for BB(7) is... nothing other than handwaving... but it sort of means it needs to walk up the "operator strength" ladder very quickly... it eventually needs to grow faster than any computable operator we define (including, for example, up-arrow^n, and up-arrow^f(n) for any computable f).

My gut feeling is that the growth between 47 million and 2^^2^^2^^9 is qualitatively larger than the growth between 2^^2^^2^^9 and graham's number in terms of how strong the operator we need is (with gramah's number being g_64 and g here being roughly one step "above" up_arrow^n). So probably we should have BB(7)>Graham's number.

pinkmuffinere5 hours ago

I can’t edit my original comment anymore, but replying to say I went on a Wikipedia binge and I think you’re right. Thanks for humoring me and helping me learn!

pinkmuffinere13 hours ago

Apologies if this feels adversarial, but I think your informal proof has an error, and I think I can explain it!

Your proof rests primarily on this assertion:

> BB has to grow faster than any computable sequence.

This is almost true! BB(n) has to grow faster than any computable sequence _defined by an n-state Turing machine_. That last part is really important. (Note that my restatement is probably incorrect too, it is just correct enough to point out the important flaw I saw in your statement). This means that up-arrow^f(n) _can_ be larger than BB(n) — up-arrow^f(n) is not restricted by a Turing machine at all. As an easy example, consider f(n) = BB(n)^2.

You may still be right about BB(7) being bigger than Graham’s number, even if your proof is not bulletproof

btilly8 hours ago

No, the original was correct.

Any computable sequence S(n) must be computed by a specific finite program of fixed length.

Once n gets big enough, BB(n) will include the function S(2^n), and therefore will exceed that computable sequence.

Given computable sequences may exceed BB(n) for a finite number of terms. But eventually BB(n) will outgrow them, and will never look back.

gpm11 hours ago

Math's a cooperative endeavor, I want to know if I'm wrong!

I'm not sure I understand the distinction you're trying to make though, and I'm not sure it's right...

The argument that BB has to grow faster than any computable sequence is that if we have a computable f(n) where for all n f(n) > BB(n) then we can solve the halting problem by simulating turing machines of size n for f(n) steps and checking if they halt. Even if we can't prove f(n) > BB(n) the mere existence of this f would mean we could solve the halting problem (even though we couldn't prove we had done so).

I agree my "proof" (intuition really) rests on that assertion.

> As an easy example, consider f(n) = BB(n)^2.

This, like BB(n), isn't computable?

+2
pinkmuffinere9 hours ago
adgjlsfhk112 hours ago

one of the things that does come out of BB is that BB(n)^2>>BB(n+c) for some very small constant c (I would be surprised if c>2)

+1
pinkmuffinere12 hours ago
Scarblac19 hours ago

It boggles my mind that a number (an uncomputable number, granted) like BB(748) can be "independent of ZFC". It feels like a category error or something.

tromp18 hours ago

What makes BB(748) independent of ZFC is not its value, but the fact that one of the 748-state machines (call it TM_ZFC_INC) looks for an inconsistency (proof of FALSE) in ZFC and only halts upon finding one.

Thus, any proof that BB(748) = N must either show that TM_ZF_INC halts within N steps or never halts. By Gödel's famous results, neither of those cases is possible if ZFC is assumed to be consistent.

Diggsey15 hours ago

I think what's most unintuitive is that most (all?) "paradoxes" or "unknowables" in mathematics involve infinities. When limiting ourselves to finite whole numbers, paradoxes necessarily disappear.

BB(748) is by definition a finite number, and it has some value - we just don't know what it is. If an oracle told us the number, and we ran TM_ZFC_INC that many steps we would know for sure whether ZFC was consistent or not based on whether it terminated.

The execution of the turing machine can be encoded in ZFC, so it really is the value of BB(748) that is the magic ingredient. Somehow even knowledge of the value of this finite number is a more potent axiomatic system than any we've developed.

edanm3 hours ago

> BB(748) is by definition a finite number, and it has some value - we just don't know what it is. If an oracle told us the number, and we ran TM_ZFC_INC that many steps we would know for sure whether ZFC was consistent or not based on whether it terminated.

This doesn't sound right to me.

You can prove that ZFC is consistent. You could do it today, with or without the magic number, using a stronger axiom system. If an Oracle told you that BB(748) = 100 or whatever, that would constitute proof that ZFC is consistent.

But it wouldn't negate the fact that BB(748) is independent of ZFC, because you haven't proved within the axioms of ZFC that ZFC is consistent, which is what makes it independent.

> I think what's most unintuitive is that most (all?) "paradoxes" or "unknowables" in mathematics involve infinities. When limiting ourselves to finite whole numbers, paradoxes necessarily disappear.

I might be missing something, but all of these assertions deal with finite whole numbers, not infinity. Unless you count a Turing machine running forever an infinity, in which case, it seems counterintuitive to me that encoding a while loop that runs forever somehow makes paradoxes appear.

waluigi7 hours ago

It’s even more counterintuitive than you let on! If you are working in ZFC along with the axiom “ZFC is consistent” then there’s no issue: just a normal number[1]. Where things get really strange is in ZFC plus the axiom “ZFC is inconsistent”.

This already sounds like an inconsistent theory, but surprisingly isn’t: Godel’s second incompleteness theorem directly gives us that Con(ZFC) is independent, so there are models that validate both Con(ZFC) and ~Con(ZFC). The models that validate ~Con(ZFC) are very confused about what numbers are: from the models perspective, there is a number corresponding to a Godel code for the supposed proof of inconsistency, but from the external view this is a “nonstandard number”: it’s not not a finite numeral!

Getting back to BB(748): what does this look like in a model of ZFC + ~Con(ZFC)? We can prove that the machine internal to the model will find that astronomically large Godel code, so BB(748) will be a nonstandard number. In other words, you can tell if a 748 state machine will terminate in this model: you’ve just got to run it for a number of steps that’s larger than every finite numeral!

[1]: unless there’s some machine that with 748 that enumerates theorems of ZFC+Con(ZFC) but that’s a different discussion.

raincole8 hours ago

BB(748) is a finite number, but I'd argue its magic also comes from infinites: the fact some Turing Machines run forever and never halt.

joelthelion5 hours ago

Is it? If it's not possible to prove that it's the best solution to bb(748), does it even exist in any meaningful way?

zmgsabst13 hours ago

You’d know the value in a more powerful system than ZFC (as it includes such an oracle) — but you can already reason about ZFC in a more powerful system.

We already have more powerful systems, but what causes the inability to self-reason is exactly that power: only first order logic can prove its own consistency. Once you get powerful enough to model arithmetic, you can build statements with self-referential weirdness.

I don’t see it as a paradox, but as growth: a sufficiently rich system can pose questions which suggest a richer system — and thereby scaffold up the universe hierarchy.

edanm2 hours ago

> Thus, any proof that BB(748) = N must either show that TM_ZF_INC halts within N steps or never halts. By Gödel's famous results, neither of those cases is possible if ZFC is assumed to be consistent.

Isn't it more accurate to say that any proof that BB(748) = N in ZFC must either show that TM_ZF_INC halts within N steps, or never halts?

Meaning, it's totally possible to prove that BB(748) = N, it just can't be done within the axioms of ZFC?

woopsn12 hours ago

Does the fact that BB(k)=N is provable up to some k < 748 mean that all halting problems for machines with k states are answered by a proof in ZFC?

Scarblac17 hours ago

I don't understand, surely if we assume ZFC is consistent then it's obvious that it won't halt? Even if its consistency can't be proven, neither can its inconsistency, so it won't halt. Or is that only provable outside of ZFC?

I guess it's also hard when we have an arbitrary Turing machine and have to prove that what it's doing isn't equilavent to trying to prove an undecibable statement.

tromp17 hours ago

If we assume ZFC to be consistent, then Gödel's 2nd incompleteness theorem tells us that it cannot prove its own consistency. So in particular it cannot prove than TM_ZFC_INC will never halt.

LegionMammal97817 hours ago

If you believe that ZF is consistent, then you believe that the machine cannot halt (assuming you trust its construction). But you cannot write a proof in ZF that the machine cannot halt. Such a proof must include a new axiom "ZF is consistent", or some stronger axiom.

Xcelerate18 hours ago

It boggles my mind that we ever thought a small amount of text that fits comfortably on a napkin (the axioms of ZFC) would ever be “good enough” to capture the arithmetic truths or approximate those aspects of physical reality that are primarily relevant to the endeavors of humanity. That the behavior of a six state Turing machine might be unpredictable via a few lines of text does not surprise me in the slightest.

As soon as Gödel published his first incompleteness theorem, I would have thought the entire field of mathematics would have gone full throttle on trying to find more axioms. Instead, over the almost century since then, Gödel’s work has been treated more as an odd fact largely confined to niche foundational studies rather than any sort of mainstream program (I’m aware of Feferman, Friedman, etc., but my point is there is significantly less research in this area compared to most other topics in mathematics).

hyperpape17 hours ago

This ignores the fact that it is not so easy to find natural interesting statements that are independent of ZFC.

Statements that are independent of ZFC are a dime a dozen when doing foundations of mathematics, but they're not so common in many other areas of math. Harvey Friedman has done interesting work on finding "natural" statements that are independent of ZFC, but there's dispute about how natural they are. https://mathoverflow.net/questions/1924/what-are-some-reason...

In fact, it turns out that a huge amount of mathematics does not even require set theory, it is just a habit for mathematicians to work in set theory. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Reverse_mathematics.

Xcelerate17 hours ago

Yeah, I’m quite familiar with Friedman’s work. I mentioned him and his Grand Conjecture in another comment.

> This ignores the fact that it is not so easy to find natural interesting statements that are independent of ZFC.

I’m not ignoring this fact—just observing that the sheer difficulty of the task seems to have encouraged mathematicians to pursue other areas of work beside foundational topics, which is a bit unfortunate in my opinion.

hyperpape16 hours ago

I agree most working mathematicians have limited interest in foundational topics. To me, that seems harmless enough.

> approximate those aspects of physical reality that are primarily relevant to the endeavors of humanity.

This is the comment that made me think that you were saying we needed more work on foundations for math as it is used in the sciences, and that doesn't match my understanding. Did I read it differently than you meant it?

azan_18 hours ago

> As soon as Gödel published his first incompleteness theorem, I would have thought the entire field of mathematics would have gone full throttle on trying to find more axioms.

But why? Gödel's theorem does not depend on number of axioms but on them being recursively enumerable.

Xcelerate17 hours ago

Right, Hilbert’s goal was (loosely speaking) to “find a finitely describable formal system” sufficient to “capture all truths”. When Gödel showed that can’t be done, that shouldn’t imply we just stop with the best theory we have so far and call it a day—it means there are an infinite number of more powerful theories (with necessarily longer minimal descriptions) waiting to be discovered.

In fact, both Gödel and Turing worked on this problem quite a bit. Gödel thought we might be able to find some sort of “meta-principle” that could guide us toward discovering an ever increasing hierarchy of more powerful axioms, and Turing’s work on ordinal progressions followed exactly this line of thinking as well. Feferman’s completeness theorem even showed that all arithmetical truths could be discovered via an infinite process. (Now of course this process is not finitely axiomatizable, but one can certainly extract some useful finite axioms out of it — the strength of PA after all is equivalent to the recursive iteration up to ε_0 of ‘Q_{n+1} = Q_n + Q_n is consistent’ where Q_0 is Robinson arithmetic).

tliltocatl18 hours ago

Gödel's theorem shows that you need an infinite number of axioms to describe reality (given that available reality isn't finite), so any existing axiomatic system isn't enough.

+1
azan_17 hours ago
throwaway815236 hours ago

> It boggles my mind that we ever thought a small amount of text that fits comfortably on a napkin (the axioms of ZFC) would ever be “good enough” to capture the arithmetic truths or approximate those aspects of physical reality that are primarily relevant to the endeavors of humanity.

ZFC is way overpowered for that. https://mathoverflow.net/questions/39452/status-of-harvey-fr...

Xcelerate23 minutes ago

I don’t understand your post. You’re linking to a discussion about the same conjecture I mentioned in another comment 11 hours prior to your comment. Did you mean to link something else?

czbot17 hours ago

Within ZFC one can prove that any two models of second order PA are isomorphic. ZFC proves that PA is consistent. ZFC is good enough to capture arithmetical truth.

cevi17 hours ago

Unfortunately no, ZFC isn't good enough to capture arithmetical truth. The problem is that there are nonstandard models of ZFC where every single model of second-order PA within is itself nonstandard. There are even models of ZFC where a certain specific computer program, known as the "universal algorithm" [1], solves the halting problem for all standard Turing machines.

https://jdh.hamkins.org/the-universal-algorithm-a-new-simple...

+1
czbot16 hours ago
red75prime15 hours ago

> It boggles my mind that a number (an uncomputable number, granted) like BB(748) can be "independent of ZFC".

It's BB(n) that is incomputable (that is there's no algorithm that outputs the value of BB(n) for arbitrary n).

BB(748) is computable. It's, by definition, a number of ones written by some Turing machine with 748 states. That is this machine computes BB(748).

> It feels like a category error or something.

The number itself is just a literally unimaginably large number. Independence of ZFC comes in when we try to prove that this number is the number we seek. And to do that you need theory more powerful than ZFC to capture properties of a Turing machine with 748 states.

ChadNauseam19 hours ago

The number itself is not independent of ZFC. (Every integer can be expressed in ZFC.) What's independent of ZFC is the process of computing BB(748).

bo102417 hours ago

I think the more correct statement is that there are different models of ZFC in which BB(748) are different numbers. People find that weird because they don't think about non-standard models, as arguably they shouldn't.

Strilanc14 hours ago

Isn't that incompatible with the models being consistent?

Suppose model A proves BB(748) = X and model B proves BB(748) = Y > X. But presumably the models can interpret running all size 748 Turing machines for Y steps. Either one of the machines halts at step Y (forming a proof within A that BB(748) >= Y contradicting the assumed proof within A that BB(748) = X < Y) or none of the machines halts at step Y (forming a proof within B that BB(748) != Y contradicting the assumed proof within B that BB(748) = Y).

I'm guessing the only way this could ever work would be some kind of nastiness like X and Y aren't nailed down integers, so you can't tell if you've reached them or not, and somehow also there's a proof they aren't equal.

Kranar12 hours ago

The issue is that X and Y are not actual natural numbers. They are mathematical objects that satisfy all the ZFC axioms and Peano arithmetic but are infinitely large. The issue is that ZFC underspecifies natural numbers.

wat1000013 hours ago

How is that possible? That implies there’s at least one specific program whose execution changes based on the ZFC model. The rules of program execution are so simple, it doesn’t make sense that they’d change based on anything like that.

+1
bo102412 hours ago
Straw19 hours ago

Sure, if someone just gives you the number, ZFC can represent it. But ZFC cannot prove that the value is correct, so how do you know you have the right number? Use a stronger proof system? Go a bit bigger and same issue.

ajkjk19 hours ago

Not an expert, but I've read about this a bit because it bothered me also and I think this is the answer:

Most of these 'uncomputable' problems are uncomputable in the sense of the halting problem: you can write down an algorithm that should compute them, but it might never halt. That's the sense in which BB(x) is uncomputable: you won't know if you're done ever, because you can't distinguish a machine that never halts from one that just hasn't halted yet (since it has an infinite number of states, you can't just wait for a loop).

So presumably the independence of a number from ZFC is like that also: you can't prove it's the value of BB(745) because you won't know if you've proved it; the only way to prove it is essentially to run those Turing machines until they stop and you'll never know if you're done.

I'm guessing that for the very small Turing machines there is not enough structure possible to encode whatever infinitely complex states end up being impossible to deduce halting from, so they end up being Collatz-like and then you can go prove things about them using math. As you add states the possible iteration steps go wild and eventually do stuff that is beyond ZFC to analyze.

So the finite value 745 isn't really where the infinity/uncomputability comes from-it comes from the infinite tape that can produce arbitrarily complex functions. (I wonder if over a certain number of states it becomes possible to encoding a larger Turing machine in the tape somehow, causing a sort of divergence to infinite complexity?)

+1
Scarblac18 hours ago
+2
dtech18 hours ago
+1
thaumasiotes13 hours ago
+1
lupire18 hours ago
thechao19 hours ago

We need to distinguish between a computer that's equivalent to BB(n), and a computer big enough to compute the value of the number that is BB(n). By (terrible) analogy: a 4004 can be made to write a finite loop that describes how many FLOPs the number 1 supercomputer can compute without, itself, being able to usefully perform the computations of that supercomputer. (The 4004 will run out of memory/addressable disk space.) Similarly, we can no longer build decidable programs in ZFC that can compute the number BB(748). Scott is saying that they now think this "disassociation" might occur at BB(7)!

vhcr8 hours ago

Nobody can give you that number, because it's way bigger than what can be represented in the universe.

nyrikki17 hours ago

To try and help people digging into this, the following helped me.

Two lenses for trying to understand this are potentially Chastain's limits on output of a lisp program being more complex than the program itself [1] or Markov's proof that you can't classify manifolds in d>= 4.

If you try the latter and need/want to figure out how the Russian school is so different this is helpful [2]

IMHO the former gives an intuition why, and the latter explains why IMHO.

In ZFC, C actually ends up implying PEM, which is why using constructionism as a form of reverse math helped it click for me .

This is because in the presence of excluded middle, every sequentially complete metric space is a complete space, and we tend to care about useful things, but for me just how huge the search space grows was hidden due to the typical (and useful) a priori assumption of PEM.

If you have a (in my view) dislike for the constrictive approach or don't want/have to invest in learning an obscure school of it, This recent paper[3] on the limits for finding a quantum theory of everything is another lens.

Yet another path is through Type 2 TMs and the Borel hierarchy, where while you can have a uncomputable number on the input tape you algorithms themselves cannot use them, while you can produce uncomputable numbers by randomly selecting and/or changing an infinite sequence.

Really it is the difference between expressability and algorithms working within what you can express.

Hopefully someone else can provide more accessible resources. I think a partial understanding of the limits of algorithms and computation will become more important in this new era.

[1] https://arxiv.org/abs/chao-dyn/9407003 [2] https://arxiv.org/abs/1804.05495 [3] https://arxiv.org/abs/2505.11773

drdeca17 hours ago

Looking at [3], they seem to argue that the system isn’t complete for the usual Gödel reasons, which, sure, it isn’t, but then they call the claim that the system fails to decide, which is a statement about probability, a “scientific fact”. This seems to me like a mistake?

Like, a TOE is not expected to decide all statements expressible in the theory, only to predict particular future states from past states, with as much specificity as such past states actually determine the future states. It should not be expected to answer “given a physical setup where a Turing machine has been built, is there a time at which it halts?” but rather to answer “after N seconds, what state is the machine (as part of the physical system) in?” (for any particular choice of N).

Whether a particular statement expressed in the language of the theory is provable in the theory, is not a claim about the finite-time behavior of a physical system, unless your model of physics involves like, oracle machines or something like that.

Edit: it later says: “ Chaitin’s theorem states that there exists a constant K_{ℱ_{QG}} , determined by the axioms of ℱ_{QG} , such that no statement S with Kolmogorov complexity K(S) > K_{ℱ_{QG}} can be proven within ℱ_{QG} .”

But this, unless I’m badly misinterpreting it, seems very wrong? Most formal systems of interest have infinitely many distinct theorems. Given an infinite set of strings, there is no finite universal upper bound on the Kolmogorov complexity of the strings in that set.

Maybe this was just a typo or something?

They do then mention something about the Bekenstein bound, which I haven’t considered carefully yet but seems somewhat more promising than the parts of the article that preceded it.

tromp16 hours ago

It looks like the authors of [3] misunderstood Chaitin. What Chaitin said about the limits of provability is that no statements of the form "K(x) > c_F" can be proven in formal system F where c_F is some constant depending on F.

nyrikki15 hours ago

I will admit that I added that cite mostly because of the very real barriers to even learning RUSS.

By the typos etc.. you. can probably also tell I was doing this on mobile, unfortunately as a passenger in a car.

To quote Chaitin’s explanation here:

> In contrast I would like to measure the power of a set of axioms and rules of inference. I would like to be able to say that if one has ten pounds of axioms and a twenty-pound theorem, then that theorem cannot be derived from those axioms.

This paper's notation does seem to be confusing, but I still think it is essentially complete with the above.

"K_{ℱ_{QG}}" would probably most commonly be L in most descriptions, a natural number that is the upper bound of complexity for provable statements in a formal system S

L is not a limit on complexity, it means that there is no formal proof for S that its Kolmogorov complexity exceeds L, for any string.

You can still prove that there are strings far more complex than L with S, and in fact there will often be far more of those strings than the ones equal to or less than L.

It is a limit on what you can prove about those strings with a greaterKolmogorov complexity in S.

Or to rewrite the above:

"There exists a natural number L such that we can't prove the Kolmogorov complexity of any specific string of bits is more than L."

Does that help or did I miss the mark on your objection?

LegionMammal97817 hours ago

Let X = "1 if ZF is consistent, 0 otherwise". Then the statements "X = 0" and "X = 1" are independent of ZF. Whether the definition of X is a satisfactory definition of a particular number is a question of mathematical philosophy.

BB(748) is very similar, in that I'd call it a 'definition' independent of ZF rather than a 'number' independent of ZF.

drdeca17 hours ago

No individual number is uncomputable. There’s no pair of a number and proof in ZFC that [that number] is the value of BB(748). And, so, there’s no program which ZFC proves to output the value of BB(748). There is a program that outputs BB(748) though, just like for any other number.

boothby15 hours ago

Individual numbers can be uncomputable! For example, take your favorite enumeration of Turing machines, (T1, T2...) and write down a real number in binary where the first bit is 0 if T1 halts and 1 otherwise, second bit is 0 if T2 halts... clearly this number is real and between 0 and 1, but it cannot be computed in finite time.

Scarblac4 hours ago

That's a number in R, obviously most of them are uncomputable (there is a countable number of Turing machines).

But for every natural number n there is a trivial Turing machine that just prints n and then halts.

drdeca14 hours ago

Pardon, I meant natural number. I should have specified.

Vecr14 hours ago

If it had a finite size it would be computable.

cvoss11 hours ago

I think your mistake is your claim that BB(748) is a natural number. For you to know that, you would necessarily have to know an upper bound for the number of steps it takes for the BB-748 machine (whichever machine it is) to halt. But you definitely don't know that.

Related: It's incorrect to claim that each machine either halts or doesn't halt. To know that that dichotomy holds would require having a halting problem algorithm.

throwaway815236 hours ago

The truth value of the continuum hypothesis is either 1 or 0 (at least from a platonistic perspective). But, it is proven to be independent of ZFC. No huge numbers involved, just a single bit whose value ZFC doesn't tell you.

LPisGood13 hours ago

BB(748) is a natural number, and _all_ natural numbers are computable.

ted_dunning6 hours ago

There is definitely a function f such that f() = n for all n ∈ ℕ.

But there is also a function g that you cannot prove whether g() = n.

Important distinction.

This means that somebody could claim that the value of BB(748) = n but you cannot be sure if they are correct (but you might be able to show they are wrong).

bo102417 hours ago

Many replies don't seem to understand Godel and independence (and one that might is heavily downvoted). Cliff notes:

* ZFC is a set of axioms. A "model" is a structure that respects the axioms.

* By Godel, we know that ZFC proves a statement if and only if the statement is true in all models of ZFC.

* Therefore, the statement "BB(748) is independent of ZFC" is the same as the statement "There are two different models of ZFC where BB(748) are two different numbers.

* We can take one of these to be the "standard model"[1] that we all think of when we picture a Turing Machine. However, the other would be a strange "non-standard" model that includes finite "natural numbers" that are not in the set {0,1,2,3,...} and it includes Turing Machines that halt in "finite" time that we would not say halt at all in the standard model.

* So BB(748) is indeed a number as far as the standard model is concerned, the problem only comes from non-standard models.

TL;DR this is more about the fact that ZFC axioms allow weird models of Turing Machines that don't match how we think Turing Machines usually work.

[1] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Non-standard_model_of_arithmet...

eapriv17 hours ago

It’s not “an uncomputable number”.

Straw19 hours ago

The category error is in thinking that BB(748) is in fact, a number. It's merely a mathematical concept.

jerf19 hours ago

No, that's one of the freakiest things about things like the Busy Beaver function. There is an exact integer that BB(748) defines. You can add one to it and then it would no longer be that number anymore.

If you are refering to the idea that nothing that can't exist in the real universe "really exists", then the "Busy Beaver" portion of that idea is extraneous, as 100% of integers can't exist in the real universe, and therefore, 100% of integers are equally just "mathematical concepts". That one of them is identified by BB(748) isn't a particularly important aspect. But certainly, a very specific number is identified by that designation, though nothing in this universe is going to know what it is in any meaningful sense.

perthmad18 hours ago

This integer only exists if you assume classical logic. Otherwise, there is no such integer a priori, and actually there is none in general.

+1
jerf17 hours ago
+1
nyssos18 hours ago
Dylan1680718 hours ago

> that's one of the freakiest things about things like the Busy Beaver function

Every sentence ever spoken and every view ever looked at is also a number. It's not a freaky thing about "things like" busy beaver, it's a freaky thing about the concept of information.

But even though everything is a number, saying "it's crazy that a number can be X" is usually someone making a mistake, using the everyday concept of numbers in their head. If you replace "a number" with "some text and code and data", people wouldn't say it's surprising that "some text and code and data" can be unprovable in ZFC.

Technically a photograph is a number, but primarily it's something else. BB(748) is the same, technically a number but primarily it's a series of detailed computer calculations.

+1
gnramires17 hours ago
Scarblac18 hours ago

There is a finite number of Turing machines of size 748. The number of them that eventually halt is thus also finite, and BB(748) is the highest number of steps in the finite list of how many steps each took to halt. It has to be a number.

We just can't prove which number it is, we don't know which of the machines halt.

Almondsetat19 hours ago

As if numbers weren't merely mathematical concepts

bmacho18 hours ago

Let S be a statement. S is called semidecidible (also: Turing recognizable, most commonly "recursively enumerable", abbreviated as "r.e.", but I hate that one) if there is a Turing machine that halts if and only if S is true.

With this definition, we can say that "ZFC is inconsistent" is semidecidible: you run a program that searches for a contradiction.

The question BB(748) =/= 1000 is similarly semidecidable. You can run a program that will rule out 1000 if it is not BB(748).

So they are in the same "category", at least regarding their undecidability.

Also, if you turn "ZFC is consistent" into a number: {1 if ZFC is consistent; 0 if ZFC is inconsistent}, you will see, that BB(748) is not very much different, both are defined (well, equivalently) using the halting of Turing machines, or, the result of an infinite search.

gylterud18 hours ago

A constructive mathematician would indeed deny that BB(748) is a well defined number. One could define it as a predicate on natural numbers, but lest we find a contradiction in ZFC we cannot hope to constructively prove that it holds for any number.

dtech18 hours ago

It's as much a number as 12

lupire18 hours ago

Only if you believe that a number you can't count is a number. You can believe that, but it's a leap.

+1
falcor8418 hours ago
MichaelDickens17 hours ago

It's known that BB(14) is bigger than Graham's number, but this new finding leads me to believe that BB(7) is probably bigger than Graham's number. Intuitively, the technology required to go from pentation to Graham's number feels simpler than the technology required to go from `47,176,870` to `2 <pentate> 5`.

tromp17 hours ago

Thanks for sharing; your post would fit well as an answer to mine about Graham's number...

sedatk19 hours ago

> Also, the left-superscript means tetration, or iterated exponentiation: for example, 1510 means 10 to the 10 to the 10 and so on 15 times.

I thought it was a typo. First time I encounter tetration.

griffzhowl18 hours ago

Continuing the theme of iteration: it was the first time I encountered pentation

tialaramex18 hours ago

One of the reasons I like the use of the number line in schools is that on the line it's more obvious when you're shown addition and multiplication and then later exponeniation that this is a pattern. With the number line, two natural questions arise and, hopefully by the time you're taught exponentiation the Math teacher knows enough math to confidently affirm the answer to both. Yes, it keeps going like this forever, that's called Hyperoperation. And yes, we did (probably) skip one, it's known as Successor-of and you were probably not explicitly shown this operator but it's the near end of that infinite succession.

When arithmetic is introduced just as a way to, for example, count money, it's more directly practical in the moment, but you're not seeing the larger pattern.

Nevermark17 hours ago

Don't forget identity. Its range is small but important!

tialaramex16 hours ago

Fair!

lbourdages15 hours ago

I've seen it before, but it was using Knuth's up-arrow notation [1], which I like because it generalizes easily.

[1] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Knuth's_up-arrow_notation

seeknotfind19 hours ago

> So I said, imagine you had 10,000,000sub10 grains of sand. Then you could … well, uh … you could fill about 10,000,000sub10 copies of the observable universe with that sand.

I don't get this part. Is it really rounding away the volume of the observable universe divided by the average volume of a grain of sand? That is many more orders of magnitude than the amount of mass in the universe, which is a more usual comparison.

Straw19 hours ago

Yes, that's right, dividing by that ratio essentially barely affects the number in a sense that 'adjacent' numbers in that notation give a much bigger change.

10↑↑10,000,000 / (sand grains per universe) is vastly larger than, say, 10↑↑9,999,999

So on system we're using to write these numbers, there's really no better way to write (very big)/ (only universally big) than by writing exactly that, and then in the notation for very big, it pretty much rounds to just (very big).

mckeed19 hours ago

With tetration you're not dealing with orders of magnitude anymore, but orders of magnitude of orders of magnitude.

Chirono19 hours ago

Exactly. This number is so so much bigger than 10^100000 or however many grains of sand would fit, that dividing by that amount doesn’t really change it, certainly not enough to bring it down closer to 9,999,999sub10

Scarblac19 hours ago

Yes, that's only some normal number amount of orders of magnitude. Even 10,000,000^10,000,000 is already so large that it doesnt matter, let alone after exponentiating _the exponent_ nine times more.

wizzwizz45 hours ago

It's the other way around: we're talking about 10^(10^(10^(10^…))) (which is vastly bigger).

lupire18 hours ago

Here's a more common example of this sort of comparison:

In significant figures, 1.0 billion minus 1.0 million equals 1.0 billion.

Nevermark17 hours ago

True but this is a ratio.

However many universes in question, there is a qualitative difference between that many empty universes (with 1 grain), and that many completely packed with grain.

Ask anybody who lives in one!

vismit20007 hours ago

Scott Aaronson | How Much Math Is Knowable? [Harward CMSA]: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VplMHWSZf5c

Recently on HN (couple of months ago): https://news.ycombinator.com/item?id=43776477

ryandrake13 hours ago

> For those tuning in from home, here BB(6) is the 6th Busy Beaver number, i.e. the maximum number of steps that a 6-state Turing machine with a {0,1} alphanet can take before halting, when run on an initially all-0 input tape.

Oh! Of course! That sure clears things up for this non-expert. This is clearly a hardcore blog for people who have been doing this kind of research for decades. Kind of awesome to stumble upon something so unapologetically dense and jargony and written for a very specific audience!

Bjartr12 hours ago

That should be enough for someone with an undergrad CS education to at least get a sense of what's going on if they haven't encountered the busy beaver problem before.

Is it niche jargon, absolutely, but to say it's only accessible to people who have put in decades is selling yourself short.

ryandrake12 hours ago

Hmm, interesting. It’s been 30 years since my engineering degree (not CS) and I’d have to look up what a Turing machine is. I think I remember one professor briefly mentioned it as “This is something the CS majors care deeply about but nobody else in the industry does.” Where I was, the CS degree was essentially a math degree dressed up in a hoodie.

Bjartr11 hours ago

> This is something the CS majors care deeply about but nobody else in the industry does

Correct, the industry cares a lot more about Software Engineering than Computer Science.

> CS degree was essentially a math degree dressed up in a hoodie.

To a first approximation, that's what it's supposed to be. CS is a field of mathematics. It's not a trade school course.

clbrmbr12 hours ago

The definition there is standard undergraduate computer science theory. Maybe not standard for software engineering though.

phs17 hours ago

So what is the richest logic whose proofs can be enumerated with only a five state TM?

LegionMammal97810 hours ago

While that question depends on what you count as an 'enumeration', there's the related question of "What's the richest logic that cannot prove the halting status of all 5-state TMs?" That is, what's the richest logic that some 5-state TM's halting status is independent of?

I've pondered that version of the question a bit, but I couldn't get very far due to my lack of expertise in first-order logic. What I do know is that Skelet #17 [0] is one of the toughest machines to prove non-halting on a mathematical level [1], so any theory sufficient to prove that Skelet #17 doesn't halt is likely sufficient to decide the rest of the 5-state machines.

[0] https://bbchallenge.org/1RB---_0LC1RE_0LD1LC_1RA1LB_0RB0RA

[1] https://arxiv.org/abs/2407.02426

tromp17 hours ago

That entirely depends on how you want to interpret a finite binary string as an enumeration of logic proofs?!

fjfaase19 hours ago

I wonder if the visible universe is large enough to write down the exact value of BB(6).

aeve89019 hours ago

If you treat the observable universe as a closed system, you could try to apply the Bekenstein bound using - R ≈ 46.5 billion light-years (radius of the observable universe) - E ≈ total mass-energy content of the observable universe

The mass-energy includes ordinary matter, dark matter, and dark energy. Current estimates suggest the observable universe contains roughly 10^53 kg of mass-energy equivalent.

Plugging these into S ≤ 2πER/ℏc gives someting on the order of 10^120 bits of maximum information content.

S ≤ 2πER/ℏc

S ≤ (2 × 3.141593 × 3.036e+71 × 4.399e+26)/(1.055e-34 × 299792458)

S ≤ 2.654135e+124

S ≤ 10^120

So, no.

kaashif19 hours ago

It definitely isn't. The amount of information you can store in the universe is something like 10^120 bits. Even if I'm off by a trillion orders of magnitude it doesn't matter.

layer813 hours ago

You’re probably referring to a state where all parts of the complete representation exist at the same time. Because if they don’t have to exist at the same time, then it might be possible to “write it down” if the universe has unbounded duration (“might” because I don’t know how the heat death plays into that). However, “at the same” time isn’t well-defined in relativistic spacetime. The sibling comments are definitely right with respect to the reference frame implied by the CMB. But I’m wondering if it wouldn’t be possible to slice spacetime in a way that actually makes a representation possible “at the same time” in some reference frame?

Dylan1680717 hours ago

Just the starting number in the article is ¹⁵10. That means it's 10^(¹⁴10). That means it has ¹⁴10 digits. So no, you can't.

Scarblac19 hours ago

It's not.

Alive-in-202519 hours ago

I want some easier to comprehend number for BB(6), in decimal notation. But it's such a massive number I would need to invent a new notation to express that. I love this new (to me) concept of tetration number representation. 10-million sub 10, what is the number?

Look at 3 sub 10 = which is (10^(10^10)). So that is 10 to the power of 10 billion. In regular decimal notation, that is a "1" with 10 billion "0"s following it. It takes 10 gigabytes of ram to represent the number in decimal notation, naively.

The number of atoms in the universe is only 10^80, or 1,000...000 (80 zeroes). 10-million sub 10 is so huge, how much ram to represent it.

This example is from https://www.statisticshowto.com/tetration-function-simple-de...

d_silin17 hours ago

Any time I see such results from computation complexity theory, I realize that any current zeitgeist of "super-intelligent AI are gods" is complete bullshit.

You can convert every atom of observable Universe into a substrate for supercomputer, you can harness energies of supermassive black holes to power it, but running a humble BB(6) to halting state would be forever out of its reach.

istjohn17 hours ago

That strawman never stood a chance.

charcircuit18 hours ago

>imagine you had 10,000,000_10 grains of sand. Then you could … well, uh … you could fill about 10,000,000_10 copies of the observable universe with that sand. I hope that helps people visualize it!

People can't visualize numbers that big. There's more ways to express numbers than just counting them. For example a single grain of sand has infinite states it can be in (there are an infinite amount of real numbers), so you could say a single grain of sand could represent BB(6). Combinations can grow exponentially, so that may be something useful to try and express it.

Xcelerate18 hours ago

At some point big numbers become much more about the consistency strength of formal systems than “large quantities”.

I.e., how well can a system fake being inconsistent before that fact it discovered? An inconsistent system faking consistency via BB(3) will be “found out” much quicker than a system faking consistency via BB(6). (What I mean by faking consistency is claiming that all programs that run longer than BB(n) steps for some n never halt.)

Dylan1680717 hours ago

If the universe rounds to the nearest Planck unit, then a grain of sand suddenly has not all that many states.

Using infinite precision to make things seem tractable is sleight of hand in my book. Stick with integers when you're describing scale.

unsnap_biceps18 hours ago

I'm confused about this example, isn't the count of grains of sand equal to the count of observable universes so it'd be a single grain of sand per universe?

heftig17 hours ago

The "about" does a lot of heavy lifting in this example. Dividing 10,000,000_10 by the number of grains that fit into one universe doesn't change it much. The 10,000,000 would get smaller somewhere in the deep depths of the decimal fraction.

NooneAtAll319 hours ago

If you want to learn about actual Busy Beaver results, I suggest reading https://www.sligocki.com/ instead

Unlike Aaronson, he actually is on the forefront of Busy Beaver research, and is one of the people behind the https://bbchallenge.org website

tedunangst18 hours ago

Can you elaborate on what's wrong with this post?

moralestapia18 hours ago

>Unlike Aaronson, he actually is on the forefront of Busy Beaver research [...]

Extremely bad ad hominem, I enjoyed Aaronson's read, nothing wrong with it.

refulgentis18 hours ago

Gently, seconding peer: that is not ad hominem :)

Colloquially, I understand it's easy to think it means "saying something about someone that could be interpreted negatively" because that's the context it is read in it when it is used.

The meaning is saying a logical argument is incorrect because of who wrote the argument.

moralestapia17 hours ago

The wording implies that Aaronson does not know what he's talking about.

>If you want to learn about actual Busy Beaver results [...]

This is saying there is no discussion of the results in the article, which is not true.

>Unlike Aaronson, he actually is on the forefront of Busy Beaver research [...]

This implies Aaronson has no (or lesser) authority on the subject and suggests we should listen to somebody else who purportedly has more.

Nowhere in @NooneAtAll3's comment is there an argument made against/for the contents of the article, an example of that would be:

"Aaronson mentions X but this is not correct because Y" or something along those lines.

Instead, the comment, in it's full extent, is either discrediting (perhaps unintentionally) and/or appealing to the authority of people involved. That's ad hominem.

charcircuit17 hours ago

But the comment is not just saying something negative.

It is implying that claims from the article like "Then, three days ago, Tristan wrote again to say that mxdys has improved the bound again, to BB(6)>9_2_2_2" are not real results. The justification for these not being real results is solely based off whether author is actually on the forefront of research.

+1
refulgentis17 hours ago
lupire18 hours ago

That's not ad hominem at all.

renewiltord17 hours ago

I don’t get it. What’s wrong with the post? And https://arxiv.org/abs/1605.04343 is interesting, no?

lupire18 hours ago

https://www.sligocki.com/ hasn't posted since April, and the very first link on that blog is a link to... Scott Aaronson.

refulgentis18 hours ago

Could I bother you for some more info?

I spent 5 minutes trying to verify any link in the post above links to Scott Aaronson, or mentions him, and found nothing. :\ (both the siglocki, and when I found nothing there, the busy beaver site)

alexeldeib18 hours ago

The "first" link (after the home button) on bbchallenge is the header bar link to https://bbchallenge.org/story which cites Aaronson in the first sentence (double first!). I would not describe it like OP for someone trying to find the actual link ;)

"One Collatz Coincidence", the 2nd story on the blog, also mentions Aaronson